This work is available here free, so that those who cannot afford it can still have access to it, and so that no one has to pay before they read something that might not be what they really are seeking. But if you find it meaningful and helpful and would like to contribute whatever easily affordable amount you feel it is worth, please do do. I will appreciate it. The button to the right will take you to PayPal where you can make any size donation (of 25 cents or more) you wish, using either your PayPal account or a credit card without a PayPal account. |
Requiring Judicial Recusal from Presiding Over Cases Involving Election
Contributors The Supreme Court 5-4 ruling (Caperton v. A.T. Massey Coal)
that judges must recuse themselves from hearing cases involving litigants who
have contributed large sums to their elections is particularly interesting in
light of the controversy surrounding President Obama’s and Judge Sotomayor’s
comments about having empathy[1] for
economically and socially disadvantaged people affected by judicial
rulings. Clearly, economically
disadvantaged people are not normally able to have contributed significant
campaign contributions to any elected judge. Many, such as Senator Jeff Sessions (R – Alabama), minority
chair of the Senate Judiciary Committee, have said that the law is the law and
should apply equally to everyone with empathy having no proper place in
deciding cases. The law is all that
should decide cases. That would be reasonable: In Caperton v. A.T. Massey Coal, the Supreme Court for the
first time in history decided that large campaign contributions, though
previously allowed under an interpretation of the first amendment’s guarantee
of freedom of speech[3], violated
the due process clause of the Constitution.
Previously judges were to recuse themselves from cases involving
conflicts of interest, such as owning stock in the company of one of the
litigants, having a relative who worked for the litigant, having worked
recently for a law firm that worked for one of the litigants (particularly on
matters involving the case before the court), having close personal ties to one
of the litigants, etc. but campaign contributions were not grounds requiring
recusal. The minority opinion was that this ruling was too vague to
be of legal value and would require answering many questions about its
application in describing which kinds of cases counted and which did not. In a separate minority opinion Justice Scalia
argued it would open the courts to a flood of groundless litigation. These
rationales are themselves interesting and I will address them also. What I find relevant to the Sotomayor controversy is that it
is incomprehensible to me that anyone with any sensitivity to citizens who do
not, and who particularly do not have the means to, make large contributions to
a judge’s election could think due process in terms of fairness and the
appearance of fairness was not jeopardized when such a citizen was opposed in
trial by an individual or organization that had contributed large sums of money
to the judge’s election. The fact that a
benefit or attempted benefit for a judge occurred prior to his ruling rather
than after it (as would be the case if a judge or one of the judge’s relatives
or good friends had a financial stake in the ruling) seems to be a distinction
without a significant difference – and is like saying that it would be okay to bribe
a judge presiding in a case as long as you pay him/her before s/he renders a
decision rather than after, and as long as there were no actually stated quid pro quo. A judge’s being “beholden” or even grateful
to a contributor in any way, shape, or form seems likely to at the very least
dispose the judge to favor the litigant who made the contribution. A trial in
which a judge rules on behalf of someone who has bestowed an important favor is
one that at best is tainted and reasonably suspicious.[4] While it is theoretically possible that a judge can rule fairly
and without bias on the merits of a case where one, and only one, of the
litigants has made a substantial contribution to his/her election, and while
theoretically there may be a way of discerning that, that a judge will clearly rule without favoritism
when siding with the litigant who made the contribution, is believed at most
only by the wealthy who make such contributions (if them) or judges who have
benefited, or stand to benefit from them in the future. In most cases it will be difficult to tell
whether the decision was prejudiced or not, and so it is better not to have the
question arise in the first place.
Judges should recuse themselves in cases where one of the litigants, and
only one of the litigants, gave substantial election help. In cases where both litigants contributed somewhat
equally toward the judge’s election, judges should not have to recuse
themselves because any bias due to such contributions cancels itself out. Attorneys probably know or suspect there is likely judicial
bias favoring contributors to judges’ election campaigns. It is more than likely that attorneys who
will have to try cases before the judge who is elected at least sometimes support
or make contribution to judges’ campaigns as a self-defensive cost of doing
business, rather than because they have any particular regard for the
candidate’s judicial philosophy or intellect.
They may not so much be trying to curry favor as they are trying to
avoid disfavor. Often, though not
always, individuals who stand to benefit from a judge’s election make contributions
to all the viable candidates in order to cover or hedge their bets. I suspect that a litigant who made a
substantial campaign contribution only to the opponent of a judge who was elected and is now trying the case,
would not be so disposed to see his/her trial as being fair as s/he is when the
backed candidate won the election. It is
simply difficult to imagine how a trial can be fair when one and only one
litigant in it has done a substantial favor for the presiding judge; and it is
difficult to imagine how any judge cannot see that it is or seriously appears
to be, unfair, even if s/he believes s/he can be impartial. One expects judges to have, if not empathy
for the litigant who cannot make such a contribution, at least the sensitivity
to see the problem. As to Chief Justice Roberts’ dissenting point that “this
ruling was too vague to be of legal value and would require answering many
questions about its application in describing which kinds of cases counted and
which did not”, it is not atypical for the Court to make decisions that do not
answer all the questions involving a law.
They do so whenever they make very narrow rulings; i.e., rulings on
narrow points or matters of law. Furthermore, the Constitution itself has proved over the
centuries to be “vague” enough to require “answering many questions about its
application”, often by the Supreme Court itself. If the law were always perfectly clear and
consistent, courts would only be necessary to determine matters of fact, not
matters of law. And insofar as law concerns justice and not just rules for
the sake of rules, as the Preamble to
the Constitution expresses it, “in Order to form a more perfect Union,
establish Justice, insure domestic Tranquility, provide for the common defense,
promote the general Welfare, and secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves
and our Posterity” there have to be judgments rendered that bring formal rules
into compliance with serving those general and imprecise, but nevertheless
intelligible, purpose, insofar as law, precedent, and reasonable interpretation
allow. This is particularly true because
the wording of rules is notorious for not embodying their full intent
(correctly), and because even the most carefully worded laws often leave unintended
and unanticipated loopholes. So the fact that courts will have to refine this ruling is
not grounds for not making it. As to Justice Scalia’s contention that the ruling will bring
a flood of groundless litigation, our laws do that anyway. That is a by-product of our legal
system. But as court’s refine their
opinions in ensuing precedents, such litigation is increasingly decided in
lower courts. And, it is not clear how ruling that elected judges do not
need to recuse themselves from deciding cases where one of the litigants made
substantial campaign contributions, prevents other ways of bringing lawsuits which
try to eliminate or discourage judicial favoritism. Whether Justice Scalia sees the problem or
not, or simply thinks it is a groundless issue with no possibly meritorious
argument, the problem still exists and needs to be addressed in some way. If Justice Scalia is correct that it is an
issue for legislation, not judicial decisions, any legislation that tackles the
problem will still likely end up in court, and Justice Scalia will probably
consider some of those cases groundless as well, whether they are or not, and
whether his colleagues on the Court agree or not. There is, after all, a difference between a
case’s being groundless and its simply not having sufficient merit, or
perceived merit, to win a favorable ruling.
If merely losing were the criteria for being groundless, every case ever
brought to court which had a losing side would be groundless and should not
have taken up Justice Scalia’s time.
[1]
Some of this controversy could be semantic.
If empathizing with a litigant
is taken to mean favoring or being on the side of the litigant out of feelings
of shared circumstances, it would be inappropriate for a judge. But if empathy
means being sensitive enough to understand each litigant’s plight and
circumstances, which is the meaning I am using here, then the view expressed in
this paper presumes that such sensitivity actually is preferable for judges to
have and should, if anything, be required or expected whenever feasible, not
forbidden. [2]
In sports and games, for example, “the rules are the rules”, and they apply to
everyone who plays them – which is all that is required to make them fair in
that sense of fairness. But games are
voluntary, so it does not matter that a rule might give strange or unfair
results in some other way. If in
basketball, a team were able to find a coordinated 10 foot tall player who
could just simply stand near the goal and receive high lobs that s/he converts
to easy dunk shots, helping his/her team win every game, that would not be
unjust in any way in the sport, though it might make the game boring, and
probably would result in an off-season rule change that prevented such height
from being an overwhelming advantage that drives away fans from opposing
team. Even in sports there is some
extrinsic sense of “justice” apart from merely “universally even application”,
but intrinsically in sports “rules are rules” and as long as they apply equally
to everyone, nothing else is involved in determining their fairness, even if
they temporarily give one team or player a decided advantage over others. Real life should not operate that way. For example, consider a “poll tax” requiring
a fee be paid by voters. That can be
fair in the sense of being universally applied, but it is unfair in that it
effectively disenfranchises voters who cannot afford to pay it. Courts should
not be totally blind to the latter aspect – the de facto results of a given law
– even if in some kinds of laws de facto results should not be determining, as
perhaps in business license fees. [3]
That campaign contributions are considered tantamount to free speech is clearly
a “stretch” in ordinary language terms of what constitutes “speech”. Perhaps it is the judicial understanding of
“money talks”. If a person with a significant sum of money at his/her command
wishes to further a candidate’s election chances because s/he agrees with the
candidate’s positions, then there should be some truly anonymous mechanism to
promote that position with monetary or other contributions. But insofar as a judge knows where such
contributions came from, there is no way to distinguish and disentangle
“freedom of speech” from “currying favor”. [4]
While normally when a litigant has a special relationship with a judge, the
relationship is considered potentially unfairly beneficial for the litigant,
the opposite possibility is worth considering.
Suppose, for example, in Cheney v. USDC for District of Columbia, that on the duck hunting trip in question
shared by Justice Scalia and Vice President Cheney, Vice President Cheney had
accidentally shot Justice Scalia in the face, as he did later a different
hunting companion on a different trip. Would not the attorneys for Mr. Cheney
have sought for Justice Scalia to recuse himself. |