This work is available here free, so that those who cannot afford it can still have access to it, and so that no one has to pay before they read something that might not be what they really are seeking. But if you find it meaningful and helpful and would like to contribute whatever easily affordable amount you feel it is worth, please do do. I will appreciate it. The button to the right will take you to PayPal where you can make any size donation (of 25 cents or more) you wish, using either your PayPal account or a credit card without a PayPal account. |
False Cause, Misdiagnosis, and the Fallacy of Affirming the Consequent I recently overheard two physicians discussing the following
medical mistake. A teenage girl had come
down with mono that even after the fever and other signs went away, left her
with a lump in her neck area. At least
one, if not both parents were physicians and they told her it was just from the
mono. Her pediatrician also had said
that was what it was. The girl complained
about it repeatedly but every physician said the same thing until years later
one did a biopsy and found out it was a malignancy that had been growing from
the beginning and then spreading. The physicians discussing the story lamented about the case
and felt bad for the parents (and the girl) but seemed to think it was just a
dumb, uncharacteristic, accidental mistake on the part of the physicians
involved. I want to argue here there is strong logical and
psychological reason for the error and that it is indicative of many kinds of
mistakes, not only in medicine but in all areas of life. The reasons the misdiagnosis seems dumb in
hindsight are that in hindsight mistakes are always more clear than at the
time, but in this particular case we also, by just knowing the story is being
told and likely has a point, know to look for the less than obvious and normal
diagnosis. The same people who hear the
story and say “they should have checked for that” would have made the same
mistake, most likely, if faced with the same combination of circumstances with
a patient. Physicians, like everyone
else, rarely look for a different explanation once they have thought up one
that fits the facts, unless new facts present themselves that confound or deny
that explanation. This is particularly
true if the second explanation is so much less likely to occur than the first. There are a number of common reasons for why this error was
made however. What happened in the
above case was that because the parents and the physicians knew she had mono
and knew that mono easily caused swollen nodes, some of which stayed swollen or
hard, they had a satisfactory
explanation for the lump and didn’t seek a different one because they thought
there was no need. The first reason they thought there was no need was that it
would be rare for this lump to have formed independently of the mono but at the
same time as the mono. Thus, by Occam’s
Razor, you don’t seek two causes for phenomena when one will serve (in this
case mono and the lump), particularly if the one cause is highly likely (occurs
with the phenomena frequently) and the two causes occurring simultaneously are
highly unlikely since the second cause – in this case the malignancy – is very
unlikely on its own. The problem with using
Occam’s Razor is that it will be wrong sometimes, and the simpler explanation
will not be the correct one. That only
shows up though if you discover differentiating circumstances. In science that occurs when someone notices
that some (usually newly discovered), phenomena cannot be explained by the
hypothesis that accounted for other previously known phenomena thought to be
relevant. Then a different explanation
has to be sought. But not until then.
However, that shows that in any situation, it is at least logically possible
that the initial explanation may not be sufficient. When it is known there are likely multiple possible causes
for a sign or symptom, physicians know to do differential diagnoses. The above kind of misdiagnosis tends to occur
when multiple causes are thought to be too improbable to have to rule out. Unfortunately, in a case where one of the
possible causes, though rare, can be deadly, it does need to be ruled out
because one should not only taken into account probabilities of a diagnosis
being wrong but also the value and significance of the possible alternative
causes/explanations for the sign or symptom.
Even if a potentially fatal cause has only a 1 in 10,000 chance of
occurring, you need to rule it out in every case because you don’t know which
case is the 1. If there are 100,000
cases of the symptom’s appearing every year, and none of them are investigated
because each is considered to be highly unlikely, ten people will die
unnecessarily. The second logical and psychological cause of this mistake
is the error of “false cause” or often a corollary error known by its latin
designation: post hoc ergo propter hoc,
which means that if something occurs after an event it was caused by the
event. In most logic books, the examples
are clearly not causally related and are examples of either stupidly jumping to
a conclusion or examples of how a silly superstition can begin – such as an
athlete’s winning or playing well after having had an unusual food the night
before, and so he wants that same food before every event; and when he plays
well, he attributes it to the food. The
problem is that the fallacy occurs even in cases that seem to be causally related because of frequency of combined
occurrence, as in the mono and swollen nodes case, or because there seems to be
a reasonable causal connection; that is, the connection seems to make sense
even if it is not correct, e.g., attributing a misdeed to greed on the agent’s
part because he had a vested interest in the result that occurred, whereas it
might simply have been a mistake on his part (and he may not even have known
the result would be in his favor). The
equivalent mistake of this sort in a medical diagnosis would be to know that a
result could occur from some biochemical pathway that exists, and so it “makes
sense” that the first condition caused the second, even though another
(unconsidered) pathway would also give the result. Unfortunately, third, there is a different, even more
prevalent and psychologically compelling fallacy that also applies, which is
the fallacy of affirming the consequent, which means that one presumes that one
can tell a cause from a result, forgetting that since other causes can have the
same result, you therefore cannot tell the cause from the result. Specifically in logic the fallacy is stated
in the following form: Now clearly in this case, Lincoln was murdered, but we don’t
know it from the information in 1 and 2.
We know it from historical accounts of the story of his assassination by
John Wilkes Booth. If you were to
substitute the name “Jones” for Abraham Lincoln, you would not know whether the
conclusion was true or not in the above argument. That shows that argument form is never
reliable, even when the conclusion happens to be correct: In science, in medicine, in everyday life, we often commit
this fallacy, and often are right purely by coincidence or because we know
something else that is not stated in our reasoning. Most of the time, for example, the conclusion
of the following argument would be true: This argument never works; it is always invalid, and what it
serves to substitute for is either of the following two arguments, which, if
stated would more likely have led to the correct diagnosis: Argument B: As explained in my essay “The Nature of the Logic of
Confirmation in Science”, that is the form I believe accurately describes
and validly justifies the scientific method.
The invalid justification of the scientific method is the one most often
given, which is the fallacy of affirming the consequent: But if argument B had been explicit in the minds of the
parents or the pediatrician, there is a chance they would have realized the
conclusion -- that the lump’s being malignant is highly improbable – meant it
still needed to be checked because they would possibly have realized that even
if improbable, it needed to be definitely ruled out because it was so
potentially dangerous. E.g., the reason
you don’t play Russian roulette – even with only 1 bullet among 1000 guns is
that the improbability of shooting yourself with the bullet is more than
compensated for in a bad way by the harm caused if it did occur, and since
there is no real “up side” of pulling the trigger if the bullet is not in that
chamber, the low probability of the risk does not make it worth taking. Similarly in the neck lump case, the low
probability of the risk the lump is malignant does not justify taking that risk
by not checking to rule it out as a possibility. And that might have been realized by the
physicians involved if they had just thought about the logic of the diagnosis
correctly. But that is difficult to do,
particularly if one is unaware of the problem, as most people, even intelligent
and educated people, are not. And it is
difficult to do in the rush of everyday circumstances, even when one is
intellectually aware of the problem. |
This work is available here free, so that those who cannot afford it can still have access to it, and so that no one has to pay before they read something that might not be what they really are seeking. But if you find it meaningful and helpful and would like to contribute whatever easily affordable amount you feel it is worth, please do do. I will appreciate it. The button to the right will take you to PayPal where you can make any size donation (of 25 cents or more) you wish, using either your PayPal account or a credit card without a PayPal account. |