This work is available here free, so that those who cannot afford it can still have access to it, and so that no one has to pay before they read something that might not be what they really are seeking. But if you find it meaningful and helpful and would like to contribute whatever easily affordable amount you feel it is worth, please do do. I will appreciate it. The button to the right will take you to PayPal where you can make any size donation (of 25 cents or more) you wish, using either your PayPal account or a credit card without a PayPal account. |
The Essential Goal of Medicine and the Moral Role of the Physician in Regard to Euthanasia
Rick Garlikov
I wish to contend here that it is incorrectly narrow to view
the roles of physicians as being the 1) healing or the promotion of (faster) healing and 2) prevention of
illness and injury where possible.
Instead, these are specific ways to pursue or achieve the larger, more
general and more appropriately considered goal of ending, alleviating, or
preventing physical and psychiatric suffering in the most constructive possible
way(s). It is the prevention or remedy
of physical and psychiatric suffering in the best and most reasonable way that
is, or should be, and should be considered to be, the primary purpose of
medicine. Healing or promoting healing
is normally the most reasonable way to achieve that goal, but in cases where healing
or creating or extending life conflict with preventing or alleviating
suffering, preventing or alleviating suffering should be, and should be
considered to be, the paramount duty or overriding obligation. If healing were the only appropriate goal, physicians and
medicine would not need to be interested or involved in alleviating or
preventing suffering at all, and they should not treat any patients they cannot
heal or improve. There would be no more
need to use anesthetics today then there was prior to their discovery, at least other than to render patients immobile
during precise or delicate surgery if there were no other way to do it
effectively. And insofar as medicine
does not cure the common cold, there would be no need to alleviate the discomfort
of colds or any illness, and it would be inappropriate for patients to ask for
treatments to do that. But clearly, a
role of medical practice is to alleviate unnecessary discomfort where that is
possible and harmless to do. It has even
been said that the role of physicians in cases where they have no (speedy) cure
or rehabilitative remedy for an injury or illness is to recommend treatments
which simply distract the patient from his/her condition while nature takes the
time to do the healing. If I am correct, then justifiable euthanasia, if it exists,
is not antithetical to the role of modern medicine and physicians, as it would
be if healing is the only or primary goal. If I am correct, one can not use the
physician’s role as healer to justify prohibiting physician-assisted suicide in
those cases where suffering is not bearable, not able to be alleviated by any
means short of euthanasia, not worth enduring and not able to be made worth
enduring. While it is true that
physician-assisted suicide conflicts with healing the patient, it does not
conflict with alleviating patient suffering of that (essentially unendurable)
sort in the best, most constructive, or only possible way when healing is
not possible and is not an option, and
where terminal sedation is not as reasonable or fair as active or passive
euthanasia. (It is not terrible pain and suffering themselves that justify euthanasia I am not arguing here that euthanasia/physician-assisted
suicide is ever right. I am simply
contending that if it is wrong, that cannot be because it conflicts with the
role of medicine and being a physician.
Whether it is the most reasonable way to end or alleviate suffering in
any actual, specific cases, or even in any logically conceivable ones, is open
to reasonable discussion and determination, but if it is, then it should be
permissible. Moreover, I am not arguing that a particular physician
should be required to euthanize patients against the physician’s conscience, if
the patient has some other recourse to euthanasia or a physician who will
assist. However, there may be circumstances
where it would conceivably be morally wrong for a physician to refuse a patient
euthanasia if that means making the patient have to endure unbearable
meaningless suffering for no good reason.
It could conceivably be as wrong to refuse euthanasia as to refuse a
patient painkillers or anesthetics for no good reason just because the
physician thinks in a particular case pain is important to suffer and it is not
his/her role to prevent or alleviate it.
There are, of course, instances where pain is wrong to prevent -- as
when doing so masks it as a sign of some more serious problem that is important
to know or where painkillers would cause more harm than good. But making someone endure pain or suffering
one could end, particularly terrible pain or suffering, for insufficient or no
good reason would be as wrong as it would be to inflict torture on someone for
insufficient or no good reason. Omitting
to end or prevent unnecessary and unreasonable suffering, when it is easily
within your power to do so, is as
morally reprehensible as actively causing unnecessary and unreasonable
suffering. Failing to prevent a toddler
from running out into traffic when all you have to do is block its path to the
street is as morally culpable as is pushing it off the curb or sidewalk into a
busy street. And this is not a matter of intentionality. The principle of double-effect which
allegedly permits foreseeable harm in the form of unintended collateral damage
is unjustified. Intentions are not what
justify acts with foreseeable bad consequences.
If they did, then every act with foreseeable bad consequences would be
justified by intending to do whatever good consequence the act might
conceivably have. “Your honor, I did not
intend to kill those children I ran over when I drove 60 mph past the stopped
school bus with its lights flashing in the residential area; I
was only trying to get to my girlfriend’s
house faster. And yes, I did know that I would likely kill one of them;
that was clearly foreseeable. But since I only foresaw it and
didn't intend it, my speeding past the stopped bus in that residential
area was not wrong.” There are some right acts with foreseeably
harmful consequences, but those acts are right, not because of the intentions
of the person committing them, but because failing to do them would, say, cause
even more harm or would violate an important right or prior or more important
obligation which overrides the harm done.
Therefore, the distinction between terminal sedation (where a dying
patient is given sufficient morphine to render him/her unconscious, though it
will also hasten their death by shutting down vital systems sooner) and
euthanasia is a false one. Whether one
foreseeably hastens death by intending to render a person permanently unconscious
in order to end his/her suffering is morally no different from intentionally
hastening death to achieve the same end.
The real determining factor when you know your action will hasten the
person’s death is whether it is right to
hasten the person’s death or not, and why or why not, and if so, what the best
way is, and why. In line with both these last two paragraphs, once the
determination is made that a patient’s death should be allowed to occur to
alleviate their suffering, surely active euthanasia is more humane and right
than passive, at the point that the suffering to be eliminated is
occurring. If a patient is dying and is
at the point where their dying would be best for them, then it is folly to employ
a method that will prolong their life, and particularly if it also increases
their suffering, through, say starvation and further deterioration and
debility. There is a difference between
euthanizing pets and euthanizing people because pets don’t have future plans,
dreams, or hopes and expectations they hope to live to see or accomplish, so
the following is not meant to be an analogy justifying euthanasia of
humans. But it is meant to be an analogy
that justifies active rather than passive euthanasia when euthanasia is right
for either human beings or pets: you
would never agree to let an animal -- whose time had come to be put down --
simply starve to death over the coming month, rather than being euthanized as
soon as it could be made comfortable and every last thing done for it that you
wanted to do in order to give it ‘a proper goodbye’. |
This work is available here free, so that those who cannot afford it can still have access to it, and so that no one has to pay before they read something that might not be what they really are seeking. But if you find it meaningful and helpful and would like to contribute whatever easily affordable amount you feel it is worth, please do do. I will appreciate it. The button to the right will take you to PayPal where you can make any size donation (of 25 cents or more) you wish, using either your PayPal account or a credit card without a PayPal account. |