This work is available here free, so that those who cannot afford it can still have access to it, and so that no one has to pay before they read something that might not be what they really are seeking. But if you find it meaningful and helpful and would like to contribute whatever easily affordable amount you feel it is worth, please do do. I will appreciate it. The button to the right will take you to PayPal where you can make any size donation (of 25 cents or more) you wish, using either your PayPal account or a credit card without a PayPal account. |
The Flaw of Legalism in
Society and Education A kind of legalism, or formalism, is increasingly pervading society
in general and education in particular, to the detriment of both. There is a serious
problem with governance by formal rules or laws alone. Following the letter of
the law without regard for its spirit, and without general understanding of its
intent, does not normally produce the most desirable result. Formal systems do not recognize a “spirit” of
the rules apart from their explicit wording, and yet the underlying general understanding
and significance of rules cannot itself be expressed within the system as a
formal law or rule. Legalism has always been a problem because it creates
loopholes on the one hand and too narrowly restricted behaviors on the other, and
because it often impedes pursuit of discovering and doing what is actually
right.[1] It even, on occasion, when
rules are bad or simply misstated, prevents people from being able to recognize
or adhere to the truth or the right behavior because that will result in their
ostracism or punishment. This is
becoming increasingly important and problematic today as more and more education
and corporate policies mistakenly claim, without argument, that: Claim 1 (the moral version): Rules of conduct need to
be thoroughly and explicitly stated in order for people to know what they are
expected to do and in order to legitimately be able to hold people accountable if
they do not do it. Corollary to Claim 1: If a person can state
explicitly the behavior that is expected of him/her, then s/he knows what is
expected. Claim 2 (the educational version): What is to be learned
needs to be thoroughly and explicitly stated in order for students to know what
they are to learn and in order to be able to hold them accountable if they have
not learned it. Corollary to Claim 2: If a person learns and knows how to state
explicitly the information s/he is expected to know, then s/he has learned it and
knows it. I believe these claims and corollaries are false. They are bad psychology, bad educational
policy, and mistaken ethics and legal theory.
I contend they lead to an unacceptable adherence to “letters of the law”
rather than its spirit, and that over time, application of this fashionable
conventional assumption embodied in these claims and corollaries fosters an
endemic erosion of good work and meaningful effort by the better part of a
generation of people who otherwise would have done much better, but who instead
do no more than is minimally prescriptively required of them, and who, for the
most part, even worse, do not even realize there is more they could be and
should be doing. The principle that all
knowledge and understanding can be made explicit and can be transmitted to
students by the teacher’s saying, and the students’ learning, the right words
is simply false, as is the claim that this is the way teaching and learning
needs to be done and to be demonstrated. There are at least two ways in which these claim and corollaries
are false: Regarding (1), the human mind is able to extrapolate general ideas
and principles from specific examples, even if those general ideas or
principles are not themselves described in words, and even in many cases when
those general ideas or principles are not even (yet) able to be described in words.
For example, when we teach children color terms, such as red, we may point
to a tomato, to a mark made by a red crayon, to the red crayon itself, to a
ripe red apple, and to picture of a red fire truck, and say “these are all
red”. We may need to point to non-red things of the same sort and say they are
not red. Normally, at some point, most children will get the concept we are
trying to teach and they will then be able to identify many other red things
even though the shades may be different.
They may not do it perfectly; they may, for instance, have trouble
knowing whether or not to call magenta things red or not, or seeing why
“magenta” crayons have their own name. They may not know quite when red shades
into pink. They may not be sure whether
strawberry blond hair is red or not. In
short, certain cases, particularly borderline cases may be difficult for them
at least at first. There may be other kinds of cases or concepts/behaviors that are
difficult for children to understand.
When I was young and we visited someone who gave me a kind of food I
didn’t like, I immediately said it didn’t taste good. My father told me later that was wrong and
that you should eat what people serve you and not say it tastes terrible. The next time that happened we were visiting
my aunt and uncle at their farm, and they gave me a glass of milk that tasted
terrible. But I drank it and just
figured it was the kind of milk they had or that “country milk” on a farm
tasted different from city milk. A bit
later that afternoon, one of my cousins complained that the milk tasted bad
(which I knew was wrong of him to do), but my father who was next to him took
it and smelled it and said “Don’t drink it; it has spoiled.” And they opened up
a fresh bottle for him. Then my father
realized I had drunk my glass, and he demanded to know why I had drunk a whole
glass of rotten milk. I, of course,
pointed out that he had told me not to say anything bad about the way food
tasted and to just accept it and eat it.
He said “Not when it has spoiled!” and, of course, I didn’t know what
that meant or that there was some sort of exception to the rule he had given
me. But even today in a restaurant, for
example, if I try a new food for the first time and it tastes terrible, I then
have a problem because I don’t know whether it has an ingredient that has
turned “bad” or whether it was accidentally incorrectly prepared or whether it
is perfectly okay but just something I do not enjoy the taste of. So I have to decide whether to ignore it or
whether to call the waiter over to find out whether something is wrong or
whether it is “just me”. That becomes
very embarrassing sometimes because they may not understand I am not
complaining or wanting a replacement but just trying to find out whether there
is something wrong or not with what I was served – and, if so, then of course I
want a replacement, but if not, then that is my fault not theirs and I will
simply pay for my mistake and know not to order that again for myself because
it is simply a taste I do not care for.
I do not wish to be given special treatment but just reasonable
treatment depending on whether it is a matter of an objective problem with the
food or just an issue of my subjective taste, which is not a problem for which
they or anyone is at fault, and for which they should not be penalized. Many concepts, which might be called “ultimately simple” concepts
that are not themselves verbal, such as color terms, cannot be defined in terms
simpler than themselves. The way we
teach or define these terms is by pointing to examples, as with colors. But we do this with regard to other terms or
concepts too, particularly with basic sensory concepts, such as bright, dark,
dim, smooth, rough, loud, inaudible, soft (sounding or feeling), acrid, sweet,
sour, fragrant, etc. It is impossible to
define or describe these terms or concepts to anyone who would be devoid of the
senses to experience them because they are terms that refer to those
experiences. But there are non-sensory, intangible, or abstract concepts that resemble
each other in ways which are difficult or impossible to correctly express or
define merely in words without reference to examples from which the learner has
to extrapolate for him or herself the idea intended: good, bad, right, wrong,
beautiful, ugly, happy, sad, depressing, exciting, boring, logically valid,
invalid, sexual, desirable, undesirable, pleasant, unpleasant, etc. Many of these concepts we have trouble
defining, but not particularly recognizing or using, such as Justice Potter
Stewart’s claim about pornography, concepts such as frustration, death (in some
cases[2]), health, anger, love,
other emotions, hunger, balance in a painting, being humorous, etc. There are
often disagreements or confusions in borderline or complex cases, but even in
some simple cases it is difficult to define the concepts in words that really
capture all and only what one has in mind.
Yet we use and discuss these concepts all the time with, for the most
part, a basic understanding of each other, even when we disagree about an application
– as, for example, about whether a particular joke is funny or not, even though
we both know what it means for a
joke to be funny. The concept may be
clear even though difficult to express in words. And the main point of the above is that we can know and teach and
learn these concepts, and be accountable for knowing them under reasonable
conditions, even if they cannot be formally described or defined in some way. We can discover, and we can learn to
understand, concepts that transcend the examples we used to discover or teach
them. Moreover, a student who truly wants to learn difficult concepts,
and a teacher who truly wants to teach them, will work hard to overcome the
limitations of words, and will seek ways to convey and to understand the concepts
apart from the words used in the process.
And that effort will, or should, normally be apparent, as will its
lack. In short, having the right words
to directly convey in a formal way what one is trying to teach is not always
necessary for teaching or learning it, as long as some reasonable and
reasonably effective means of teaching it is employed. For it to be fair for students to be held
accountable for learning or for people to be held accountable for doing what is
right, they have to be exposed to the kind of teaching or experience from which
it would be reasonably expected they could and should learn it. And, of course, they have to have the
abilities or faculties to learn if they try, and the ability to try. Good teaching will, of course also try to
give incentive to the learning and make it more interesting and enjoyable to
work on whenever possible, but that is not always able to be done or even
necessary in some cases. And it does not mean precise, prescriptive verbal
descriptions are necessary. Moreover, precise, prescriptive verbal descriptions are also not
always sufficient. Regarding point 2 on p.2, that we often have verbal
descriptions without comprehension, one can state words without realizing their
full meaning or range of application. For example, to be able to state Newton’s
Laws of motion does not mean one can do classical mechanics problems in
physics, even when one has been taught to analyze motion in terms of forces and
vectors, etc. Stating someone else’s
understanding is not the same thing as understanding something oneself (see www.garlikov.com/Interpretation.html)
or, as it is sometimes put “internalizing the understanding” or in a modern
phrase that I think is particularly meaningless, “taking ownership of that
knowledge”. There are thousands of
concepts that have been developed that students can state without really
comprehending: moles in chemistry, place-value in math, other numerical
relationships or theorems in math, Archimedes’ buoyancy principle, validity in
logic, terms of a contract, legal concepts in general, traffic rules, driving
instructions, airplane flying instructions, instruction manuals for assembling
things or using software, the national anthem of one’s country or the “Lord’s
Prayer” or “Pledge of Allegiance”[3]. In other words, being able to read words out
loud (in the sense merely of pronouncing them correctly), or recite what one
has been told, does not by itself mean one understands it or that one can apply
it in a useful or meaningful way. This often becomes obvious not only in
classrooms but in situations where, for example, people well-versed in some
body of moral pronouncements do not see that they apply at work in behavior
toward their employees or customers or in behavior toward other drivers on the
road. Now I want to begin
consideration of Claim 1 by examining a point made by George Washington in his Farewell
Address, though he stated it in a way that I think needs some further analysis in
order not to be misleading: Let
it simply be asked: Where is the security for property, for reputation, for
life, if the sense of religious obligation desert the oaths which are the
instruments of investigation in courts of justice? And let us with caution
indulge the supposition that morality can be maintained without religion.
Whatever may be conceded to the influence of refined education on minds of
peculiar structure, reason and experience both forbid us to expect that
national morality can prevail in exclusion of religious principle.[i] Since I believe
that in some important sense morality can
be learned and perfectly well-practiced without religion, because there are
plenty of morally good atheists and agnostics, and because many people are
morally good in situations not addressed by their religions, I want to first
offer an interpretation of his claim that supposition should be indulged with
caution. I believe that his next sentence means that it cannot be expected that
the general population will be moral without religious convictions, not that no
one can be moral without religious convictions or principles. And I suspect, but cannot prove, that what But whether we
are talking about religion or secular law, when a system of behavioral
governance is established that is based solely or primarily on what the least
respectful, least conscientious, and least responsible people need in order be
controlled or held accountable, that system bodes ill for the rest of the
population for two reasons. The first is
that it is extremely difficult, if not impossible to state explicitly how
people ought to behave in every conceivable situation. Second, any system designed to prevent amoral
and immoral people from doing harm will normally not allow those who are
scrupulous and conscientious the full range of freedoms they need to flourish
and contribute. Such a system will neither help unconscionable persons
understand their full responsibilities nor prevent behaviors they will believe
they can get away with doing because those behaviors are not explicitly
forbidden, even if they know those behaviors are wrong. And such a system will also not provide any
incentive for irresponsible people to become conscientious. This has
importance for more than just criminal behavior. We are seeing the fruits of legalistic
policies in education in college, graduate level, and post graduate work today,
as the so-called “Y generation” shows interest only in minimally meeting
requirements, and does even that in a legalistic way that argues if they have
not violated any specific rule or law, they are not culpable for any of their
actions, no matter how bad those actions are.
The view among students
frequently is that if they “show up” for class and turn in assignments,
they should pass or get an “A” regardless of the quality of their work, because
quality is not explicitly described. If
a teacher does not tell them exactly how to make their work be good, it is the
teacher’s fault if the work is poor.
Basically many students think that if they are not given the exact
answer to fit the way the question is asked, they are not responsible for not
knowing it. The exaggerated
humorous example of this was given in an episode of the Damon Wayans television
situation comedy My Wife and Kids
when the teenage son was reminded he continuously made poor behavioral choices
and his response was “You are still talking about that one situation, but, as I
said then, “no one ever told me not to pee out of my (upstairs) bedroom window
… and I didn’t know you and mom were outside below it”. A more realistic
but still often perversely humorous manifestation of it is the behavior of high
school students who scour the student handbook of rules in search of loopholes
that will allow them to perform acts they know will aggravate the
administration – that is, acts they know are wrong-- but which will allow them
to escape punishment since the act will not be proscribed by the rules. And
when the administration mistakenly believes there can be no punishable
transgressions without a breach of prior stated rules, the only administrative
recourse is to add that rule to next year’s handbook. This is a repetitious process that basically
only serves to fatten the handbook of student rules, but does little to alter
student behavior. However in this case
students do know better, but are simply exploiting their knowledge in light of
a weak and silly administrative policy.
These sorts of acts tend to occur in cases where administrators
generally unreasonably enforce unreasonable rules and earn the disrespect of
students who wish to retaliate by playing the rules game, meaning that if
administrators or teachers are going to make students live by rules strictly as
they are written, students are going to make them suffer for rules not written
or not properly written. It is students’
way of saying it should be obviously false to administrators that an act is
wrong if and only if there is a specific rule against it It is my
contention that administrations could prevent this kind of behavior whether it
is malicious or in jest by, instead of invoking endless, often petty rules,
having a policy something to the effect that students are expected to behave ethically,
including, but not limited to respecting others and the rights of others, and
that any student who willfully does anything wrong that s/he ought to know is
wrong, will face consequences commensurate with the seriousness of their
offense. More about this form of policy momentarily,
but it should be clear that when students do this sort of thing, they
understand the difference between what is right or wrong on the one hand and
what the rules state on the other. It is
only the administration that believes one cannot know what is right or wrong,
and be held accountable for doing what is wrong, without reference to
previously established rules printed in a handbook.[4] Just as the ninth
amendment to the United States Constitution points out there are rights beyond
those enumerated in the Bill of Rights, it would be wise, I believe, for any
list of rules to point out there are bad behaviors besides those enumerated
which will be punished if there is good reason to believe the person should
have known better than to do them. More serious is
the individual, corporate, or governmental use of legal loopholes to get away
with behaviors known to be wrong but which are not specifically illegal and
thereby punishable under the law. In
some cases, in civil suits, juries will often recognize this type of behavior
for what it is, and if possible under even the slightest pretense or
interpretation of the law, will award huge damage awards against a corporation
that they believe seriously, knowingly and intentionally, mistreated and took
advantage of someone who purchased their product or services, particularly
under cover of a technical aspect of the law or in expectation of low customary
previous damage awards. When a company
feels it is cheaper to do the wrong thing and pay a low damage award if they
are found at fault in a civil suit, and juries find out that was the
calculation made for their business decisions, then juries tend to point out
emphatically that was a callous and wrong judgment for which the company will
be economically punished much more severely than they expected. And this is part
of the case I believe Washington probably had in mind in his Farewell Address,
except that he seemed to have thought moral (and religious) people would not do
what is wrong just because it is not illegal, because their behavior would be
guided by a higher principle than mere compliance with the letter of the law. That meant that laws with strong teeth (i.e.,
serious punishments for breaking them), and morality based on religious
punishment, were only necessary in order to try to make scoundrels at least
have to think twice before willingly harming others or the public fabric. For those without conscience, justified fear
of punishment and justified fear of severe social sanctions would have to serve
as a deterrent as much as possible. But for the rest
of us, that is normally not necessary. Conscience
and awareness of right and wrong serve better than threat of punishment as a
deterrent. Very few of us refrain from burglary or murder simply because it is
against the law or because we would be punished if caught and convicted, or
because we might be consigned to hell.
We refrain because we know it is wrong, not because we think we cannot
get away with it. Many acts are not
illegal, and yet we refrain from them simply because we know they would be
wrong – whether keeping found money whose owner we can identify or keeping excess
change given to us in error or cheating on our golf score. We do things for
others without reward and often without recognition, merely because it is
right, not because it is required by law.
A friend of mine was buying a lot of clothes on sale in a major upscale
department store, and was completing the purchase as the store was already
closed. When she exited, they had to
unlock the door by hand to let her out. After
she was well out of the store, it occurred to her something seemed wrong with
the total amount of the purchase. She
checked her sales receipt, and noticed that the girl who had waited on her and
who had been talking the whole time, had missed some $300 worth of
merchandise. She was already out of the
store. The store was closed. The mall was
closing. It was not the city in which she lived, and she was due to fly home early
the next morning. She could have simply left and had a real bargain. But instead she went back to correct the
error, and had to demand to be let back into the store by a staff who did not
want to open the door to her. It would
have been easier to have walked away, but she didn’t. And there are millions of people like her;
the people Washington had in mind. She
had not shoplifted; the salesperson had removed all the store alarm devices,
and had bagged the merchandise for her. She had broken no laws, but she knew
the right thing to do was to pay the proper amount. She did not want to have the mistake in her
favor any more than she would have wanted the store to have made the same error
in their favor and charged her too much.
She did not want to be the beneficiary of someone else’s error any more
than she wanted to be the victim of one.[5] But she was of a
generation, like most generations until today, who were taught not just to
follow rules (though they were supposed to follow rules – at least morally good
rules), but were taught to “do the right thing” which involves more than just
following rules, and which sometimes requires disobeying immoral rules (as the
Nuremburg trials pointed out for those who seemed to think doing what is
directed, or required by law, absolves them from moral culpability when they do
wrong). “Doing the right thing” is an
open-ended dictum that requires insight, effort, experience, reason, thought,
sensitivity, and hard work. It is much
more difficult to understand and to heed than is simply following rules. Many of us learned to distinguish right from
wrong behavior by trial and error -- receiving admonishment at best or
punishment at worst, usually without trial, when we erred. Of course, the serious
problem of punishment without specific laws is that anyone can then be brought
up on charges for acts that there was no reason to believe were wrong, and that
may not even be wrong. While laws are
not foolproof methods of preventing punishment for morally innocent acts (or
even some morally right acts such as the intentional breaking of immoral laws),
they at least give some warning about
what a community will not tolerate whether it is actually intrinsically morally
wrong or not. To avoid the spectacle of criminal charges brought randomly by
personal whim, the Moreover, the
line between prosecuting people for breaking those and only those laws which
are explicitly stated, and prosecuting people for behaviors that are not
expressly forbidden is not as clear a line as might be thought. As I have written in the essay “Law and Order and Morality” (http://www.garlikov.com/philosophy/LOM.html)
the television series Law and Order
portrays a prosecutorial philosophy that tries to prevent “loophole”
miscarriages of justice by arguing that an obviously immoral act can, in many
cases, be interpreted as illegal under a law that was enacted for a totally
different purpose. The idea is that if
someone who has done something obviously wrong cannot be convicted under a law
most directly related to his/her action, their action can be interpreted to
fall under another law that they will have broken if the interpretation holds
up in court. What this does, given the
plethora of laws enacted, is to make the criminal justice system somewhat
closer in practice to a system of moral or natural law, though with more
constraints. Still, there will be a
tension between prosecutorial whim and necessary flexibility. But the point is that the issue of
institutional or legal governance by means of specific rules/laws versus a more
philosophical and moral principles approach is a serious issue that has serious
consequences. And I believe we are
seeing some of those consequences now play out badly in institutional settings,
particularly educational systems or schools, where it is mistakenly believed
that conduct needs to be specified in advance in order to be fairly expected
and in order to be punished fairly in its breach. There are two
things I want to add to what I have said already in regard to law: (1) although
some laws and contracts require specifically stated obligations, law does not
generally require acts of kindness or benevolence, or even all acts of
responsible behavior, that morality does.
The law does not normally require one to benefit others even if it would
be easy for you to do so. And even
though law recognizes negligence, the threshold is normally very different from
what would morally be considered negligence. The law allows people to get away
with behaviors that their parents or society would typically hold to be unacceptably
irresponsible. For example, parental
legal obligations do not require one to spend quality time with one’s children
as long as one is not neglecting their physical needs. The law does not require you to read to your
children or to take them to the zoo or to otherwise enrich their experiences,
enhance their education, or to help and inspire them to lead productive lives.
The law does not require sales clerks to be helpful or pleasant or in many
cases even to wait on you in a store. (2) Without a
sense of right and wrong there would be no incentive to amend or rescind bad
laws or to resist immoral ones that ought not to be followed. The trials at Nuremburg made clear that
immoral orders are not to be obeyed. By
extension, the same would be true of following rules or laws that are immoral. But if following the law was the only
requirement, then there would be no reason or incentive for changing the law or
saying it is wrong and needs to be disobeyed even whenever it is clearly
immoral, particularly when it seems to serve the majority and harms mostly the
minority or otherwise powerless. There
has to be a moral basis for certain laws or there would be no reason or
motivation to create them. Again then,
Washington’s view (as I interpret it) is, I think, correct, that law alone
without [religious or secular] morality and a sense of obligation to others, would
be inadequate to enhance or even protect the social fabric. Without morality, without personal moral
conscientiousness, people would be less likely to obey laws they thought they
could get away with breaking, and they would not be obligated to go beyond the minimal
duties prescribed by law, which are relatively few when compared with what is actually
morally obligatory. Relevance to Education There are a
number of ways in which Claim 2 and its corollary adversely affect education,
but the basic point is that it promotes students becoming passive readers and
listeners -- passive recipients of information-- and that is not the same thing
as learning. A passive reader is only a small step above a lazy or careless
reader. Claim 2 and its corollary also
delay or hinder student maturity and the kind of conscientiousness for going
beyond what one is simply told to do. Moreover,
telling students only those things they need to know for a test[6] is not teaching, except in
those cases where what needs to be learned is complete and self-contained, as
in learning a particular procedure such as assembling an engine, performing a
specific surgical technique, or cooking a particular recipe. But even in cooking, merely following recipes
is not necessarily being a good cook. In
cooking and in performing surgery one needs to know more than just a particular
algorithm if one is going to achieve optimal results, especially when some
variation may be necessary under unexpected circumstances. In those cases, a deeper underlying
understanding is usually important. Knowing
the procedure perfectly is necessary but not always sufficient. And one cannot likely improve upon an engine
design if all one knows is how to follow a procedure for assembling that
engine; one must usually have some idea of the principles involved in its
working. Achieving only minimal understanding should not normally be the goal
of learning or teaching. Students need to strive for more than that, and they
need to be held to a higher standard and told up front that they will be held
to a higher standard that itself will not be explicitly spelled out, but the
implication of which they should nevertheless readily understand. Students often
want to know “what they have to study” for a test, or what they have to do to
get a higher grade, and by that they mean they want very specific directions,
tantamount to being told the answers or told what to say or what to do in order
to receive extra credit. If you give
them questions they can answer using the material they have been assigned
(e.g., an “open book test”) they will say they cannot find the answers in that
material if it requires them to make deductions from (i.e., “think about”) what
has been presented in the material. Even worse, if you do not tell them
specifically which part of which assignment an issue is addressed, they
frequently say they have not been able to find the answer. If you tell them the answer is not to be
found, but to be deduced from what they are to read, they do not understand
what you mean and think that is not fair.
They want to be told what they are supposed to know, meaning what they
are supposed to say, and they will memorize it and say it back, either by
directly copying it or by stating what they think it says, whether they
understand it correctly or not. Mere surface
knowledge becomes particularly problematic when the material is complex,
because just repeating specific things others have said does not mean one
understands the material. For a simple
instance, suppose a woman tells her husband she will have to work late and will
not be able to leave her office until around 7pm and won’t be home till 8. He might perfectly well be able to repeat
that and understand she will be home around 8pm and not before. But if he does not understand the
ramifications of what that means, he may not realize he has to pick the
children up from school, bring them home, feed them dinner, help with their
homework, let the dog out and also feed it, and perhaps have a dinner prepared
for his wife when she does get home. He
might even say he didn’t know that was what she meant when she said she was
working late, even though he perfectly well knows he has two young children who
attend school miles away, that they do not ride the bus, that they need to get
home, and that though they are fairly independent workers, they do not always
understand their homework assignments and may need some monitoring in order to
do it correctly. And even though he
knows the dog stays indoors during the day and needs to be let out as early in
the afternoon as possible. If he does
not “think about” what his wife’s being home late signifies, it does not matter
that he can repeat what she said “Yes, I heard you; you will not be home until
around 8 tonight.” “Open-ended
concepts”, those which cannot be precisely defined in words very easily or that
are difficult to understand just from the words alone, are particularly difficult
to teach students educated under the influence of Claim 2 and its corollary,
because if you give them examples, they cannot get past them to generalize or
extrapolate to other cases. They do not
actively try to find the underlying relationship that makes those examples
work. It is as though you were teaching
them the color red by showing the crayon, the tomato, the fire truck, and the
red delicious apple, and the best they do in “showing other examples of red things”
is to point to other fire trucks, apples, or tomatoes. They would be unable to point out a red shirt
or the red stripes in the American flag because you never told them those
things were also red. Obviously this
case is an exaggeration, but every teacher who tries to teach abstract concepts
or relationships can point to examples that are very similar. For example, many
students, particularly of this current college generation, have great
difficulty understanding the central concept of logic –validity-- which seems
to be something very new and foreign to them.
A valid line of reasoning is one in which the evidence actually
logically implies the conclusion.
Validity is important because if you are given evidence that is all
true, but it does not logically imply the conclusion drawn from it, then there
is no good reason based only on that evidence to justify believing the conclusion. The conclusion may be true, but you cannot know it is true from the evidence
given. You may as well have faulty or
false evidence for all the good it will do you to justify believing the
conclusion. There are many ways to
explain this and there are many examples one can give of obviously invalid
arguments, those in which the evidence or premises do not imply the conclusion.
But if students cannot look beyond the example to get the intuitive idea of the
concept, and instead only try to remember the examples that are valid and the
examples that are invalid, they cannot distinguish which other arguments, even
in many simple cases, are valid and which are not. And if you give them even simple principles
or rules of inference for distinguishing conclusions that follow from those
which do not, they cannot apply the rules or even make any sense of them. There are many
examples in math, which is part of what makes math so difficult for many
people. Students have trouble with place
value, with fractions, with rate-time-distance problems, with understanding
what algebra “does” or how it works in general. Probably the main reasons
students have difficulties with “word problems” in math are that 1) they have
not learned to see mathematical relationships, but have only learned math
“facts”, 2) they have learned how to follow recipes to do calculations without
understanding how those calculations might be useful or what they mean, and 3)
word problems are open-ended in that they do not tell you or suggest what steps
you need to follow in order to solve them.
To solve them, apart from the few that are just like the ones you have
been taught to do by recipe or formula, you need to understand the math
concepts and relationships involved in them.
Then you can devise which calculations will likely yield fruitful
results, and be able to tell whether they have done so or not. This is
important because life is even more difficult and more complex than word
problems. In life, problems do not usually come labeled as problems with a
solution. Normally one might see that things are not going the way one wants,
but does not see that as being the result of a specific problem that needs to be
defined, addressed, and solved. Another
significant difference is that in school when you cannot do a word problem, you
find out about it with a low grade, but in life you just lament things are not
the way you wish they were – without realizing you might really have been able
to change that if you had figured out the root cause of the problem and figured
out how to solve it. Higher Expectations There is no good
reason that students and others should not be expected to know more than what
they are simply told or that they should not be expected to do more than is
explicitly required. The human mind is
normally quite able to extrapolate beyond mere surface level information and it
should be encouraged, and even required, to do so. While that does not mean one
should be expected to know everything, it does mean that in some cases one
should be able to be held accountable for far more than what has been
specifically stated or required. The
case should be able to be conclusively made that in some, but not all, particular
situations one ought to have learned more than one has learned or that one
ought to have behaved better than one behaved.
We can, of course, always debate in a specific case whether someone’s
behavior or knowledge is reasonable or not based on the information s/he had
available and based on an expectation of reasonable, non-negligent
conscientiousness on his/her part. And
we can sometimes disagree whether they
should have known or done better or whether they were indifferent or negligent.
But there is no reason that the courts
or schools must rigidly accept or adhere to the two claims and corollaries
stated at the beginning of this paper.
[1]
A simple example is one of the flaws in the instant replay rule in football
that requires a coach to instigate the process.
If a coach is allowed two challenges during a half, and he uses them
both, then any bad calls after that may have to stand if there is no other
mechanism for invoking instant replay reconsideration, even though television
may let every fan watching know the call was mistaken and should be remedied. [2]
The criteria for death are sometimes difficult in regard to when precisely it
occurs, particular when some parts of the body can be kept functioning by
artificial life support mechanisms. This
has significance for organ transplant, for removal from life support in cases
of irreversible vegetative state, for when to withhold treatment in a triage
situation, or when, if ever, to abandon it because it serves no real purpose. [3]
One of the curious kinds of ability to express words without seeming to
understanding them is illustrated in the Bible story of the garden and “the
Fall”. God gives Adam and Eve one rule and one rule only, don’t eat the fruit
of the one particular tree. Now, of course,
in the story there is an intervening character who tells them it is okay, and,
of course, they haven’t lived long enough to have many experiences, and they
are naïve, but nevertheless the one thing they do is to eat the fruit that was
forbidden to them. They have one rule,
and only one rule, and they break it. One can imagine that when God comes back
and finds out what they have done, He, like any other parent, says: Now I teach online courses and I see this same
behavior every term – students give answers you have written in a million
places for them not to give, including in bold font right with the question – “DO NOT GIVE THIS [spelled out] ANSWER TO
THIS QUESTION”. IT IS THE WRONG ANSWER
TO IT.” And yet, that is the answer
some of them will invariably give. It is
not that they didn’t see it, not that they can’t tell you what it said, not
that they disobeyed it on purpose or wanted to give the wrong answer. Often they even knew the right answer. It sometimes seems as in the story of the
Fall that, as Flip Wilson used to say, “the Devil made them do it.” But one still wonders how? And why did they not understand or heed or
see the significance of it. This is too
common to just be considered a pure accident or coincidence. I don’t know whether or not it is a matter
that involves not really understanding the words at some level, but there are
times that seems to be what is involved. [4]
This does not mean there shouldn’t be “coordinating” or “administrative” sorts
of policies and rules or guidelines for those behaviors that need to be
coordinated and that individuals cannot just figure out for themselves no
matter how moral, thoughtful, intelligent, or sensitive they are. The prime example in civil society would be
the coordinating conventions or rules about which side of the road to drive on,
what the traffic signals mean, etc. But
even then, and even if we list rules of forbidden driving behaviors, we also still
need a rule about reckless endangerment in general, not just a list of those
and only those specific driving behaviors that will be punished, because
someone might be driving recklessly and putting people at risk in a way no one
had thought to specifically preclude, and yet everyone can see immediately the
person ought to have known better than to do, and should be punished for doing
it. [5]
In my Introduction to Ethics I have
stated a principle that I think partially explains or justifies the obligation
not to benefit from such an error (or from finding lost money that could be
returned to its rightful owner, or doing anything that would be beneficial to
oneself in an unfair way which could be undetected or unpunished by others,
etc.) The basic idea is that it is
important to be a “deserving person”, whether one gets what one deserves or
not, for if one is not a deserving person, than one has no real claim on the
right behavior of others, as in when one loses one’s wallet or purse or a clerk
makes an error that goes undetected. If
you would not return found money to its rightful owner, you have no right to
expect someone else would return your lost money to you if they could. And my claim is not that society would be
undermined by selfish behaviors, though it probably would, or that others would
not treat you better than you deserve. My claim is that there is something
inherently important about being a deserving person, whether one gets what one
deserves or not, because what one gets is not always in one’s control (whether
for benefit or harm), but what one deserves is. [6]
See “Teaching to Tests – A Conceptual Article”; http://www.garlikov.com/teaching/tothetest.htm [i]
George Washington, Farewell Address.
The Avalon Project at |